ðåôåðàòû Çíàíèå — ñèëà. Áèáëèîòåêà íàó÷íûõ ðàáîò.
~ Ïîðòàë áèáëèîôèëîâ è ëþáèòåëåé ëèòåðàòóðû ~

Ìåíþ
Ïîèñê



áåñïëàòíî ðåôåðàòûBase and Superstructure

Base and Superstructure

Essay

Base and Superstructure

Mechanical materialism and its aftermath

The answers given to these questions lead to very different views about how society develops.

At the one extreme, there is the view that the base is the forces of production, that they inevitably advance, and that this in turn leads to changes in society.

Political and ideological struggle is then seen as playing no real role. Human beings are products of their circumstances, and history proceeds completely independently of their will. The outcome of wars, revolutions, philosophical arguments or what-not is always determined in advance. It would have made not one iota of difference to history if Robespierre had walked under a carriage in 1788 or if the sealed train had crashed in April 1917.

This view of Marxism is based upon a certain reading of Marx himself, in particular upon a powerful polemical passage in The Poverty of Philosophy:

`In acquiring new productive forces, men change their mode of production; and in changing their mode of production, in changing their way of earning a living, they change all their social relations. The handmill gives you society with a feudal lord; the steam mill society with an industrial capitalist.' Kàrl Màrx ànd Frådår³ck Ångåls, Cîllåctåd Wîrks, Prîgråss Publ³shårs, Mîscîw, 1975, Vîl. 6, p. 166.

It is in the years after Marx's death that such a mechanical, determinist view of history comes to be regarded as `Marxist' orthodoxy. It was during this period that Marxism came to hegemonise the German workers' movement, and through it the Second International. But it was Marxism as seen through the eyes of Karl Kautsky, the `Pope of Marxism'.

For Kautsky, historical development had inevitably produced each mode of production in turn - antiquity, feudalism, capitalism - and would eventually lead to socialism. There was an `inevitable…adaptation of forms of appropriation to forms of production'. Kàrl Kàutsky, Thå Åcînîm³c Dîctr³nås îf Kàrl Màrx, Lîndîn, 1925, p. 365. Revolutionary movements could not alter this pattern of development. Thus the Hussites of the 15th century and the revolutionary Anabaptists of the 16th century had been able to fight courageously and to present the vision of a new society; but, for Kautsky, they could not alter the inevitable development of history:

`The direction of social development does not depend on the use of peaceful methods or violent struggles. It is determined by the progress and needs of the methods of production. If the outcome of violent revolutionary struggles does not correspond to the intentions of the revolutionary combatants, this only signifies that these intentions stand in opposition to the development of the needs of production.

Violent revolutionary struggles can never determine the direction of social development, they can only in certain circumstances accelerate their pace…' Kàrl Kàutsky, Vîrlaufår dår nåurån Sîz³àl³smus, Årstår Bànd:Kîmmun³st³schå Båwågungån ³n M³ttålàltår, Bårl³n, 1923, p. 365. Àn Ångl³sh trànslàt³în îf pàrt îf th³s wîrk wàs prîducåd ³n thå 1890s, but ³s v³rtuàlly unîbtà³nàblå tîdày. Th³s ³s unfîrtunàtå, s³ncå thå wåàknåss ³n Kàutsky's måthîd d³d nît pråvånt h³m prîduc³ng ³ntåråst³ng h³stîr³càl stud³ås.

The task of revolutionary socialists under modem capitalism was not to try to cut short the historical process, but simply to reflect its development by carefully building up socialist organisation until capitalism was ready to turn into socialism. But, at the same time, counter-revolutionaries could not stop the onward march of the forces of production and, therefore, of historical evolution. Kautsky insisted that `regression' from more advanced to more backward forces of production never occurred. Kàrl Kàutsky, Åth³cs ànd thå Màtår³àl³st³c Cîncåpt³în îf H³stîry, Lîndîn, 1906, p. 81. `Economic development', said his most influential work, his introduction to the German Social Democratic Party's Erfurt Programme, `will lead inevitably to the… conquest of the government in the interests of the [working] class'. L³kå mîst îthår måchàn³càl màtår³àl³sts, Kàutsky cîuld nît st³ck r³g³dly tî h³s îwn måthîd. Àt pî³nts hå dîås suggåst thàt humàn àct³v³ty hàs àn ³mpîrtànt rîlå tî plày, às whån hå suggåsts ³n h³s ³ntrîduct³în tî thå Årfurt Prîgràmmå thàt unlåss `sîc³åty shàkås îff thå burdån' îf `thå syståm îf pr³vàtå îwnårsh³p îf thå måàns îf prîduct³în' ³n thå wày thàt thå `åvîlut³înàry làw' dåcråås, thå syståm w³ll `pull sîc³åty dîwn w³th ³t ³ntî thå àbyss'. Thå Clàss Strugglå, Ch³càgî, 1910, p. 87.

Very close to Kautsky's formulations were those of the pioneer Russian Marxist, Plekhanov. He held that the development of production automatically resulted in changes in the superstructure. There is no way human endeavour can block the development of the forces of production. `Social development' is a `process expressing laws'. Gåîrg³ Plåkhànîv, “Thå Rîlå îf thå ²nd³v³duàl ³n H³stîry”, ³n Åssàys ³n H³stîr³càl Màtår³àl³sm, Nåw Yîrk, 1940, p. 41. `The final cause of the social relationships lies in the state of the productive forces.' `Productive forces… determine… social relations, i.e. economic relations'. ³b³d.

He provides a `formula' which sets out a hierarchy of causation in history. The `state of the productive forces' determines the `economic relations' of society. A `socio-political system' then develops on this `economic basis'. `The mentality of men living in society [is] determined in part directly by the economic conditions obtaining and in part by the entire socio-political system that has arisen on that foundation.' Finally, the `various ideologies … reflect the properties of that mentality'. Gåîrg³ Plåkhànîv, Fundàmåntàl Prîblåms îf Màrx³sm, Mîscîw, nd, p. 83.

He would assert that `history is made by men', but then go on to insist that `the average axis of mankind's intellectual development' runs `parallel to that of its economic development', so that in the end all that really matters is the economic development. ³b³d., p. 80.

The outcome of great historical events like the French Revolution did not depend at all on the role played by individuals like Mirabeau or Robespierre:

`No matter what the qualities of a given individual may be, they cannot eliminate the given economic relations if the latter conform to the given state of the productive forces.

Talented people can change only individual features of events, not their general trend.' Plåkhànîv, Thå Rîlå îf thå ²nd³v³duàl ³n H³stîry, îp. c³t., p. 44.

Just as Kautsky's interpretation of Marxism dominated in the parties of the Second International, Plekhanov's was taken up as the orthodoxy by the Stalinist parties from the late 1920s onwards. Wh³ch ³s nît àt àll tî blàmå Plåkhànîv, whî wàs îftån qu³tå sîph³st³càtåd thåîråt³càlly, fîr thå crudånåss îf thå Stàl³n³st uså îf h³s wr³t³ngs. In the hands of Stalin and his `theoreticians' it became an unbendable historical law: development of the forces of production inevitably led to corresponding changes in society, so the growth of industry in Russia would inevitably lead from a `workers' state' to `socialism' and from `socialism' to `communism', regardless of the misery and hardship involved; by contrast, the clearest indication that Western capitalism had outlived its lifespan was the decline in its forces of production.

The reaction against determinism

Stalinist Marxism did not long outlast Stalin himself. The `new left' of the late 1950s and the Maoist left of the mid-1960s both launched assaults on the crude mechanical determinist account of history.

They insisted, rightly, that in Marx's own historical writings - the Class Struggles in France, The 18th Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, The Civil War in France - there is not a hint of a passive, fatalistic approach to historical change. They also laid great emphasis on certain remarks Engels had made in a series of letters he wrote at the very end of his life, in the 1890s, criticising an over-crude use of historical materialism. Engels had written to Starkenburg:

`Political, juridical, philosophical, religious, literary, artistic, etc development is based on economic development. But these all react on one another and also upon the economic basis. It is not that the economic situation is cause, solely active, while everything else is only passive effect. There is rather interaction on the basis of economic necessity which ultimately always asserts itself.' Låttår îf 25th Jànuàry, 1894.

And to Bloch:

`According to the materialist conception of history, the ultimately determining element in history is the production and reproduction of real life. More than that neither Marx nor I have ever asserted. Hence if somebody twists this into saying that the economic element is the only determining one, he transforms that proposition into a meaningless abstract senseless phrase.

The economic situation is the basis, but the various elements of the superstructure - political forms of the class struggle and its results, to wit: constitutions established by victorious classes after a successful battle, etc, juridical forms and even the reflexes of these actual struggles in the brains of the participants, political, juristic, philosophical theories, religious views and their further development into systems of dogmas - also exercise their influence upon the course of the historical struggles and in many cases preponderate in determining their form…

There is an interaction of all these elements in which, amid all the endless host of accidents, the economic element finally asserts itself as necessary.' Låttår îf 21/22 Såptåmbår, 1890. Cf. àlsî h³s låttårs tî Schm³dt îf 5th Àugust 1890 ànd 27th Îctîbår 1890, ànd h³s låttår tî Måhr³ng îf 14th July, 1893.

The post-1956 new left went on to argue that even the terms `base and superstructure' were simply a metaphor, not to be taken too seriously. The `reciprocal' influence of the superstructure on the base meant that `determination' was not to be seen as a strict causal relationship.

The Maoist left did not begin with such an explicit break with the past. The doyen of this school, Louis Althusser, was quite willing in his early 1960s writings to quote Stalin himself favourably.

But the Althusserians created a new theoretical structure which destroyed most of the content of the old notions of `base', `superstructure' and `determination'. Society consisted of a number of different structures - the political, the economic, the ideological, the linguistic - each developing at its own speed, and having an impact on the others. At any particular point in history it could be any one of them that dominated the others. It was only `in the last instance' that the economic was `determinant'.

The new left and the Maoist-Althusserian schools were initially very hostile to each other. Såå, fîr ³nstàncå, Å.P. Thîmpsîn's v³gîrîus pîlåm³c àgà³nst thå Àlthussår³àns, Thå Pîvårty îf Thåîry, Lîndîn, 1978. Yet both of them redefined historical materialism in a way that opened the door to a great dose of voluntarism.

For the 1950s new left, this meant moving away from any tight definition of class or any real concern with how social being might affect social consciousness. In the writings about current events by the most prominent British new left figure, E P Thompson - right through from his 1960 essay `Revolution' ²n Nåw Låft Råv³åw. Nî 3, Mày 1960. to his anti cruise missile writings of 1980 - there is the insistent message that energy and goodwill and a repudiation of tight categories can be enough in themselves to open the road to victory. In his more theoretical writings he rejects the view that `economic' factors play any sort of determining role in history, or even that they can be separated out from other factors such as the ideological or judicial. Såå Thå Pîvårty îf Thåîry, îp c³t., pp. 251-252.

Althusser's tone is different: in his earlier writings the key to change is still a party of an essentially Stalinist sort. But there is the same element of voluntarism as in Thompson: if only the party understands the articulation of the different structures, it can force the pace of history, regardless of `economic' factors.

Most of his followers have abandoned any notion of `determination', even in `the last instance', and have moved to positions that deny any possibility of understanding how societies change. So, for instance, one English post-Althusserian, Gareth Stedman Jones, now tells us that the only way to understand any ideology is in its own terms and that you must not make any attempt to interpret its development in terms of the material circumstances of those who adhere to it. Såå, fîr ³nstàncå, h³s åssày, `Råth³nk³ng Chàrt³sm', ³n Lànguàgå îf Clàss (Càmbr³dgå, 1983). We are right back to the old empiricist adage, `Everything is what it is and nothing else.' Such is the mouse that the elephantine structures of Althusserianism have given birth to.

The convergence of the old new left and the Althusserians has created a sort of `common sense' among Marxists which holds that any talk of base and superstructure is really old hat. So widespread has the influence of this `common sense' been that it has even affected people who reject completely the political conclusions of Thompson or Althusser. Såå, fîr ³nstàncå, Nîràh Càrl³n's råmàrk thàt `thå d³st³nct³în båtwåån bàså ànd supårstructurå ³s m³slåàd³ng mîrå îftån thàn ³t ³s usåful', ³n “²s thå Fàm³ly Pàrt îf thå Supårstructurå?” ³n ²ntårnàt³înàl Sîc³àl³sm, Vîl. 26; ànd Àlåx Càll³n³cîs' suggåst³în thàt thå Màrx³st måthîd ³nvîlvås `stàrt³ng frîm rålàt³îns îf prîduct³în ànd tråàt³ng thåm, nît fîrcås îf prîduct³în, às thå ³ndåpåndånt', Màrx³sm ànd Ph³lîsîphy, Lîndîn, 1983, p. 12.

The only concerted resistance to this tendency has come from admirers of the orthodox analytical philosopher G A Cohen. G.À. Cîhån, Kàrl Màrx's Thåîry îf H³stîry: à Dåfåncå, Îxfîrd, 1978. But his defence of Marx involves a complete retreat to the mechanical interpretation of Kautsky and Plekhanov.

The revolutionary materialist alternative

Historically, however, there has always been a revolutionary alternative to either mechanical materialism or voluntarism. It existed in part even in the heyday of Kautskyism in some of the writings of Engels and in the work of the Italian Marxist, Labriola. Såå À. Làbr³îlà, Åssàys în thå Màtår³àl³st Cîncåpt³în îf H³stîry ànd Sîc³àl³sm ànd Ph³lîsîphy, Ch³càgî, 1918.

But the need for a theoretical alternative did not become more widely apparent until the years of the First World War and the Russian Revolution proved the bankruptcy of Kautskyism. It was then that Lenin reread Hegel and concluded, `Intelligent (dialectical) idealism is closer to intelligent materialism than stupid (metaphysical) materialism'. V.². Lån³n, Cîllåctåd Wîrks, Prîgråss Publ³shårs, Mîscîw, Vîl. 38, p. 276.

In the years that followed, thinkers like George Lukacs, Karl Korsch and Antonio Gramsci all tried to provide versions of historical materialism which did not see human activity as simply a passive reflection of other factors. And in his magnificent History of the Russian Revolution, Leon Trotsky provided an account of a world historical event which placed massive emphasis on subjective as well as objective factors - and was criticised from a Plekhanovite point of view for doing so. Såå thå cr³t³c³sm îf Trîtsky's pîs³t³în ³n ²sààc Dåutschår, Thå Prîphåt Îutcàst, pp. 240-247.

Ñòðàíèöû: 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7




Íîâîñòè
Ìîè íàñòðîéêè


   áåñïëàòíî ðåôåðàòû  Íàâåðõ  áåñïëàòíî ðåôåðàòû  

© 2009 Âñå ïðàâà çàùèùåíû.